The Calculus of Consent: 50th Anniversary
<< Back to editing
Previous version by
a
<< Older
Newer >>
Revert to this one
search results
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
/index.php?action=ajax&rs=GDMgetPage&rsargs[]=Laissezfaire36 8.pdf&rsargs[]=0
__________________________________________________________________
Colleen
E
.
Haight
,
Andrés
Marroquín
Gramajo
and
Nikolai
G
.
Wenzel
The
Calculus
of
Consent
:
50
th
Anniversary
Introduction
James
M
.
Buchanan
and
Gordon
Tullock
wrote
The
Calculus
of
Consent
fifty
years
ago
,
in
1962
.
We
write
this
article
to
celebrate
the
occasion
.
The
three
of
us
were
graduate
students
at
George
Mason
University
when
Buchanan
and
Tullock
were
actively
participating
in
seminars
and
workshops
in
the
early
2000s
.
The
book
was
novel
in
the
sense
that
it
applied
economic
tools
—
and
,
more
specifically
,
microeconomic
tools
—
to
the
study
of
collective
decision-making
.
They
were
not
the
first
ones
in
this
endeavor
.
The
Swedish
economist
Knut
Wicksell
had
already
attempted
to
apply
economics
to
politics
,
without
much
success
.
But
his
work
inspired
James
Buchanan
.
Calculus
extended
the
assumptions
of
economic
theory
about
individuals
in
the
marketplace
to
political
actors
.
Among
their
numerous
contributions
,
Buchanan
and
Tullock
argued
that
from
an
economic
standpoint
majority
rule
was
not
“
the
best
”
criterion
to
make
collective
decisions
.
Every
decision-making
rule
generates
costs
.
They
proposed
the
unanimity
rule
as
an
ideal
,
especially
when
it
came
to
deciding
the
“
constitutional
rule
.”
Colleen
E
.
Haight
teaches
economics
at
San
Jose
State
University
(
California
,
USA
).
Andrés
Marroquín
teaches
economics
at
Universidad
Francisco
Marroquín
(
Guatemala
).
Nikolai
Wenzel
is
Visiting
Professor
at
Florida
Gulf
Coast
University
(
Florida
,
USA
).
In
1964
Buchanan
wrote
the
article
“
What
Should
Economists
Do
?”
1
In
that
article
he
reflects
on
Adam
Smith
‟
s
idea
that
human
beings
have
a
natural
tendency
to
trade
.
For
Buchanan
,
the
main
task
of
economists
should
be
precisely
the
study
of
trade
and
exchange
in
different
contexts
,
and
The
Calculus
of
Consent
does
exactly
that
:
it
looks
at
the
political
sphere
and
pays
attention
to
how
trade
occurs
.
For
this
reason
,
Buchanan
and
Tullock
‟
s
analysis
is
often
called
“
the
study
of
politics
as
exchange
.”
In
1986
,
the
Nobel
Prize
was
awarded
to
James
Buchanan
“
for
his
development
of
the
contractual
and
constitutional
bases
for
the
theory
of
economic
and
political
decision-making
.”
One
wonders
why
Tullock
was
left
out
.
James
Buchanan
and
Gordon
Tullock
have
been
exemplary
to
many
economists
,
both
because
of
their
innovative
contributions
,
and
also
because
of
their
passion
and
love
for
what
they
studied
.
Our
article
presents
the
main
arguments
in
the
book
,
part
by
part
,
and
then
briefly
presents
some
reflections
on
how
the
arguments
in
the
book
relate
to
political
economy
,
constitutional
economics
,
institutional
economics
,
and
development
economics
.
1
James
M
.
Buchanan
,
“
What
Should
Economists
Do
?”
Southern
Economic
Journal
,
30
(
Jan
1964
):
213-22
.
Laissez-Faire
,
No
.
36-37
(
Marzo-Sept
2012
):
88-96
/index.php?action=ajax&rs=GDMgetPage&rsargs[]=Laissezfaire36 8.pdf&rsargs[]=1
__________________________________________________________________
Part
I
The
Main
Ideas
of
The
Calculus
2
The
purpose
of
Part
I
of
The
Calculus
of
Consent
is
to
ensure
that
readers
all
embark
on
the
same
train
of
intellectual
discovery
.
Buchanan
and
Tullock
carefully
outline
in
the
first
four
chapters
a
few
key
parameters
within
which
they
frame
their
arguments
.
Charles
Rowley
,
in
his
introductory
comments
,
refers
to
these
parameters
as
“
hand
grenades
”
(
p
.
xi
).
This
description
is
quite
apt
,
as
the
authors
engage
in
a
creative
destruction
that
breaks
down
old
accepted
notions
of
romantic
government
,
and
use
the
first
part
of
their
book
to
clear
the
field
for
the
insights
to
come
in
later
chapters
.
Buchanan
and
Tullock
propose
the
goal
of
their
work
as
defining
not
what
“
the
State
or
a
State
actually
is
,
but
...
what
we
think
a
State
ought
to
be
”
(
p
.
3
,
italics
in
original
).
They
are
careful
to
distinguish
their
approach
to
the
political
realm
as
micro-oriented
,
positing
that
groups
do
not
make
decisions
,
individuals
do
.
Diverse
individuals
making
choices
based
on
self-interest
and
their
own
particular
preferences
do
not
always
arrive
at
a
group
decision
reflecting
the
choice
of
every
individual
.
Universal
consensus
is
recognized
as
an
ideal
standard
,
superior
to
majority
rule
,
but
also
more
costly
.
This
issue
brings
to
light
the
consent
issue
:
Does
an
individual
consent
to
a
group
decision
that
does
not
reflect
his
choice
?
The
authors
build
on
methodological
2
Page
references
to
The
Calculus
of
Consent
will
be
provided
in
parentheses
in
the
main
text
,
and
will
be
to
the
Liberty
Fund
edition
,
published
as
vol
.
2
of
The
Selected
Works
of
Gordon
Tullock
(
Indianapolis
:
Liberty
Fund
,
individualism
and
reject
an
“
organic
interpretation
of
collective
activity
”
(
p
.
11
).
As
such
they
discard
notions
of
the
general
will
of
the
people
,
as
well
as
class
distinctions
and
theories
which
involve
exploitation
of
a
ruled
by
a
ruling
class
.
The
authors
point
out
that
“
public
interest
”
as
a
concept
is
faulty
;
only
separate
interests
of
private
individuals
are
expressed
through
the
political
mechanism
.
As
for
government
,
it
is
seen
as
“
nothing
more
than
a
set
of
processes
,
the
machine
,
which
allows
such
collective
action
to
take
place
”
(
p
.
13
).
Buchanan
and
Tullock
frame
the
political
sphere
as
a
type
of
market
where
exchanges
take
place
between
individuals
seeking
to
realize
separate
goals
.
This
concept
of
politics
as
exchange
is
absolutely
revolutionary
.
Prior
political
theory
was
fundamentally
rooted
in
the
idea
of
political
actors
who
sought
the
common
good
or
acted
in
the
“
public
interest
.”
However
,
Buchanan
and
Tullock
,
having
dismissed
all
notions
of
the
existence
of
a
public
interest
,
instead
propose
that
political
behavior
consists
of
voluntary
exchanges
between
individual
political
actors
.
As
with
any
voluntary
exchange
,
it
is
not
assumed
that
one
actor
succeeds
at
the
expense
of
another
,
but
that
both
parties
to
the
exchange
benefit
.
Buchanan
and
Tullock
propose
that
the
political
sphere
is
marked
by
positive-sum
exchange
rather
than
conflict
by
individuals
who
,
while
participating
in
a
collective
decision
process
,
are
only
seeking
to
maximize
their
own
utility
.
Part
I
ends
with
a
brief
but
important
discussion
of
rationality
.
In
a
discussion
of
rank-order
and
transitivity
as
applied
to
individual
decision
making
,
the
authors
explain
the
basics
of
rationality
.
An
individual
makes
a
choice
given
his
own
personal
preferences
and
goals
.
A
successful
2004
).
choice
propels
the
individual
toward
his
__________________________________________________________________
89
/index.php?action=ajax&rs=GDMgetPage&rsargs[]=Laissezfaire36 8.pdf&rsargs[]=2
__________________________________________________________________
goal
,
an
unsuccessful
choice
does
not
.
Buchanan
and
Tullock
explain
that
when
individual
choice
is
aggregated
by
a
collective
decision
process
,
the
link
between
action
and
result
is
unclear
.
As
they
point
out
,
“[
n
]
o
longer
is
there
the
one-toone
correspondence
between
individual
choice
and
final
action
”
(
p
.
35
).
Because
there
is
no
precise
relationship
between
the
two
,
behavior
tends
to
be
less
rational
in
the
collective
.
3
Part
II
In
Part
II
of
The
Calculus
,
Buchanan
and
Tullock
seek
to
define
the
realm
of
social
choice
.
Set
against
a
backdrop
of
methodological
individualism
and
rational
actors
engaged
in
political
exchange
,
they
begin
by
explaining
the
specific
circumstances
under
which
an
individual
selects
his
decision-making
process
.
The
authors
propose
that
the
determining
factor
rests
with
the
externalities
of
the
decision
process
:
The
choice
between
voluntary
action
,
individual
or
co-operative
,
and
political
action
,
which
must
be
collective
,
rests
on
the
relative
costs
of
organizing
decisions
,
on
the
relative
costs
of
social
interdependence
(
p
.
46
,
italics
in
original
).
In
essence
,
an
individual
compares
the
costs
of
private
decision-making
with
the
costs
that
he
expects
to
be
imposed
upon
him
by
collective
decision-making
,
and
chooses
the
less
costly
method
.
After
defining
which
decisions
might
fall
under
which
type
of
decision-making
rules
,
Buchanan
and
Tullock
set
out
to
explain
how
a
society
might
select
a
system
of
decision
rules
,
or
a
constitution
.
3
See
also
James
Buchanan
,
“
Social
Choice
,
Democracy
,
and
Free
Markets
,”
Journal
of
Political
Economy
,
62
(
April
1954
):
114-23
.
They
examine
the
costs
associated
with
different
types
of
decision
rules
and
the
impact
of
decisions
made
under
the
different
rules
upon
the
individual
actor
.
Using
two
extreme
cases
,
where
either
one
individual
is
able
to
use
the
process
to
impose
costs
upon
a
group
or
where
the
entire
group
must
agree
upon
a
course
of
action
,
the
authors
illustrate
the
idea
that
there
is
no
optimal
rule
for
every
situation
.
While
a
unanimity
rule
provides
the
greatest
protection
for
an
individual
,
such
a
rule
also
imposes
great
costs
:
For
a
given
activity
the
fully
rational
individual
,
at
the
time
of
constitutional
choice
,
will
try
to
choose
that
decisionmaking
rule
which
will
minimize
the
present
value
of
the
expected
costs
that
he
must
suffer
(
p
.
67
,
italics
in
original
).
Buchanan
and
Tullock
are
explicit
about
the
trade-off
between
the
protection
afforded
by
a
more
inclusive
rule
and
the
lower
costs
of
a
less
inclusive
rule
.
Interestingly
,
while
the
authors
propose
it
is
rational
to
have
a
constitution
defining
the
decision-making
rules
,
they
argue
that
it
is
not
obvious
that
a
majority
rule
system
is
implied
by
their
analysis
.
Instead
they
propose
that
“
51
per
cent
of
the
voting
population
would
not
seem
to
be
much
preferable
to
49
per
cent
”
(
p
.
77
).
Buchanan
and
Tullock
indicate
that
the
unanimity
rule
is
the
only
rule
that
can
achieve
a
Pareto-optimal
result
,
and
as
such
,
is
decidedly
superior
.
They
concede
,
however
,
that
reaching
decisions
under
unanimous
decision
rules
is
very
costly
.
Both
at
the
time
of
writing
and
today
,
the
majority
rule
retains
tremendous
popularity
.
However
,
the
authors
say
that
majority
rule
has
value
only
so
far
as
it
is
an
imperfect
compromise
where
unanimous
agreement
would
be
too
costly
to
obtain
.
__________________________________________________________________
90
/index.php?action=ajax&rs=GDMgetPage&rsargs[]=Laissezfaire36 8.pdf&rsargs[]=3
__________________________________________________________________
Buchanan
and
Tullock
elaborate
on
the
various
costs
associated
with
collective
decision-making
.
They
acknowledge
that
even
purely
private
decisions
involve
some
cost
to
determine
an
optimal
choice
.
These
costs
remain
for
the
individuals
participating
in
collective
decisions
,
but
also
include
bargaining
costs
and
costs
related
to
group
size
and
diversity
.
Larger
groups
and
heterogeneous
groups
will
tend
to
have
higher
bargaining
costs
as
they
are
more
likely
to
lack
consensus
on
fundamental
issues
.
Part
III
The
third
part
of
The
Calculus
presents
the
analysis
of
decision-making
rules
.
Buchanan
and
Tullock
argue
that
“[
a
]
ny
rule
must
be
analyzed
in
terms
of
the
results
it
will
produce
,
not
on
a
single
issue
,
but
on
the
whole
set
of
issues
extending
over
a
period
of
conceptually
finite
length
(
p
.
116
).
The
analysis
starts
by
stating
that
votes
have
economic
value
(
otherwise
,
“„
corruption
‟
would
be
impossible
,”
p
.
117
).
If
votes
have
economic
value
,
they
represent
the
“
purchasing
power
”
of
a
voter
,
and
a
market
will
tend
to
emerge
.
The
participant
in
political
decisions
,
therefore
,
follows
economic
motives
.
Buchanan
and
Tullock
analyze
majority
rule
in
great
detail
.
One
of
the
problems
with
it
is
that
it
can
create
negativesum
games
.
This
means
that
the
majority
can
use
the
rule
to
impose
costs
on
the
minority
.
It
can
make
some
individuals
worse
off
as
a
consequence
of
the
decision
process
driven
by
the
preferences
of
the
majority
.
voting
for
something
of
which
he
disapproves
but
about
which
his
feelings
are
weak
exactly
matches
the
expected
marginal
benefit
of
the
vote
or
votes
secured
in
return
support
for
issues
in
which
he
is
more
interested
(
p
.
141
).
Trade
could
occur
in
the
form
of
side
payments
or
in
the
form
of
“
logrolling
”
(
votes
exchange
:
I
vote
for
your
preferable
option
if
you
vote
for
mine
).
This
solution
can
be
Pareto
efficient
when
all
the
voters
participate
in
the
decision
.
Logrolling
takes
place
frequently
in
Western
democracies
.
In
spite
of
being
Pareto
efficient
,
logrolling
can
nevertheless
lead
to
overspending
:
“
Each
individual
in
the
group
would
be
behaving
quite
rationally
,
but
the
outcome
would
be
irrational
”
(
p
.
136
).
Buchanan
and
Tullock
propose
unanimity
to
decide
on
the
fundamental
rule
:
the
constitutional
rule
,
or
“
the
contract
.”
Unanimity
is
the
only
decision
rule
that
does
not
allow
the
exploitation
of
the
minority
by
the
majority
,
or
vice-versa
.
It
is
the
only
rule
that
guarantees
a
symmetric
allocation
of
the
gains
(
or
costs
)
among
the
individuals
who
participate
in
the
decision
process
.
Unanimity
does
not
need
to
be
applied
to
any
single
decision
by
the
members
of
a
social
group
.
Dayto-day
decisions
can
be
taken
by
majority
rule
,
qualified
majority
rule
,
etc
.,
as
long
as
the
way
these
decisions
are
taken
is
consistent
with
the
fundamental
constitutional
rule
everybody
has
agreed
upon
unanimously
.
Unanimous
agreement
can
emerge
when
trade
is
possible
.
A
powerful
message
that
Part
III
of
the
Calculus
conveys
is
:
If
the
intensity
of
preferences
varies
among
voters
,
then
trade
is
possible
:
Potentially
,
the
voter
should
enter
into
...
without
side
payments
,
there
is
nothing
in
any
particular
voting
rule
to
insure
that
collective
decisions
will
move
the
group
to
the
Pareto-optimality
surface
or
that
such
bargains
until
the
marginal
“
cost
”
of
such
decisions
will
keep
the
group
on
the
__________________________________________________________________
91