| Liberalism and Allegory: A Tragedy | | | |
-
<< Back to editing
-
Previous version by
-
-
<< Older
-
Newer >>
-
Revert to this one
search results
-
-
-
-
-
-
-
-
-
-
/index.php?action=ajax&rs=GDMgetPage&rsargs[]=LF-48.4 Klein.pdf&rsargs[]=0
__________________________________________________________________
Daniel
B
.
Klein
Liberalism
and
Allegory
:
A
Tragedy
Yours
for
$
1
.
89
“
We
must
look
at
the
price
system
,”
wrote
Friedrich
Hayek
(
1945
,
86
),
“
as
…
a
mechanism
for
communicating
information
if
we
want
to
understand
its
real
function
.”
Hayek
’
s
talk
of
communication
enriched
economic
thinking
.
Such
talk
is
common
among
market-oriented
economists
.
In
their
textbook
,
Tyler
Cowen
and
Alex
Tabarrok
write
:
“[
P
]
rice
signals
and
the
accompanying
profits
and
losses
tell
entrepreneurs
what
areas
of
the
economy
consumers
want
expanded
and
what
areas
they
want
contracted
”
(
2010
,
85
).
Such
talk
is
both
illuminating
and
beautiful
.
But
the
price
of
eggs
communicates
:
“
Yours
for
$
1
.
89
”
–
And
nothing
more
!
If
we
are
to
be
literal
,
we
must
mind
the
element
of
communion
,
or
community
,
in
communication
.
In
its
literal
sense
,
communication
is
a
meeting
of
minds
.
The
knowledge
communicated
passes
through
us
as
commonly
experienced
ideas
,
images
,
or
notions
.
For
the
entrepreneur
computing
her
profit
or
loss
,
there
really
is
no
communication
in
the
literal
sense
,
no
meeting
of
minds
.
Whose
mind
would
she
meet
?
In
no
literal
sense
do
prices
and
other
market
phenomena
tell
entrepreneurs
what
to
do
.
We
want
to
talk
of
prices
as
“
signals
,”
but
we
must
recognize
that
they
are
not
signals
in
a
literal
sense
.
The
Prudent
Shipmaster
and
the
Invisible
Hand
Adam
Smith
illuminated
the
marvels
of
markets
by
using
simile
and
metaphor
.
He
sketched
an
aspect
of
social
coordination
:
“
It
is
the
interest
of
the
people
that
their
daily
,
weekly
,
and
monthly
consumption
should
be
proportioned
as
exactly
as
possible
to
the
supply
of
the
season
.”
The
grain
dealer
adjusts
his
prices
and
quantities
in
ways
that
conduce
to
such
coordination
:
Without
intending
the
interest
of
the
people
,
he
is
necessarily
led
,
by
a
regard
to
his
own
interest
,
to
treat
them
,
even
in
years
of
scarcity
,
pretty
much
in
the
same
manner
as
the
prudent
master
of
a
vessel
is
sometimes
obliged
to
treat
his
crew
.
When
he
foresees
that
provisions
are
likely
to
run
short
,
he
puts
them
upon
short
allowance
.
Though
from
excess
of
caution
he
should
sometimes
do
this
without
any
real
necessity
,
yet
all
the
inconveniences
which
his
crew
can
thereby
suffer
are
inconsiderable
in
comparison
of
the
danger
,
misery
,
and
ruin
to
which
they
might
sometimes
be
exposed
by
a
less
provident
conduct
(
WN
,
525
,
italics
added
).
DANIEL
B
.
KLEIN
(
PhD
,
New
York
University
)
teaches
economics
at
George
Mason
University
(
Virginia
,
USA
),
where
he
leads
the
Smithian
Political
Economy
program
.
He
is
also
the
JIN
Chair
at
the
Mercatus
Center
at
GMU
,
and
a
fellow
of
the
Ratio
Institute
in
Stockholm
,
Sweden
.
Laissez-Faire
,
No
.
48-49
(
Marzo-Sept
2018
):
58-67
/index.php?action=ajax&rs=GDMgetPage&rsargs[]=LF-48.4 Klein.pdf&rsargs[]=1
__________________________________________________________________
The
simile
of
the
prudent
shipmaster
is
a
miniature
of
the
metaphor
of
the
being
whose
hand
is
invisible
:
[
The
individual
]
generally
,
indeed
,
neither
intends
to
promote
the
public
interest
,
nor
knows
how
much
he
is
promoting
it
.
...
[
A
]
nd
by
directing
that
industry
in
such
a
manner
as
its
produce
may
be
of
the
greatest
value
,
he
intends
only
his
own
gain
,
and
he
is
in
this
,
as
in
many
other
cases
,
led
by
an
invisible
hand
to
promote
an
end
which
was
no
part
of
his
intention
(
WN
,
456
,
italics
added
).
Sometimes
a
metaphor
uses
an
animal
or
a
spirit
to
represent
human
existence
,
or
as
a
foil
to
human
existence
.
The
dictionary
defines
allegory
as
“
an
expressive
style
that
uses
fictional
characters
and
events
to
describe
some
subject
by
suggestive
resemblances
;
an
extended
metaphor
.”
The
Allegory
of
Joy
After
Smith
’
s
time
,
thinkers
fell
into
touting
fact
and
logic
,
accuracy
and
precision
,
not
allegory
.
It
was
the
occasional
figure
who
made
open
use
of
allegory
,
such
as
Edwin
Cannan
,
an
ardent
Smithian
and
editor
of
The
Wealth
of
Nations
:
“
The
reasons
why
it
pays
to
do
the
right
thing
—
to
do
nearly
what
an
omniscient
and
omnipotent
benevolent
Inca
would
order
to
be
done
—
are
to
be
looked
for
in
the
laws
of
value
”
(
1902
,
461
;
italics
added
).
The
free-enterprise
system
,
Cannan
suggests
,
leads
to
patterns
of
activities
somewhat
like
those
pleasing
to
a
benevolent
being
in
an
allegory
.
The
allegory
is
that
a
super
being
—
let
’
s
call
her
Joy
—
has
super
knowledge
,
encompassing
what
Knud
Haakonssen
(
1981
,
79
)
distinguishes
as
system
knowledge
and
contextual
knowledge
.
Joy
has
system
knowledge
and
contextual
knowledge
for
every
individual
.
The
allegory
is
that
Joy
issues
instructions
,
or
requests
,
cooperatively
,
to
each
market
participant
spelling
out
“
the
right
thing
”
to
be
done
.
Joy
tells
Bridget
the
baker
that
perhaps
she
should
buy
new
ovens
,
look
out
for
better
deals
in
flour
,
and
advertise
her
confections
.
Within
the
allegory
,
Joy
communicates
these
instructions
.
Within
the
allegory
there
is
a
meeting
of
Joy
’
s
and
Bridget
’
s
minds
regarding
these
actions
.
Bridget
is
sensible
to
Joy
’
s
benevolence
and
ethical
wisdom
,
and
feels
entrusted
to
advance
what
Joy
finds
beautiful
.
Bridget
follows
,
not
market
signals
,
but
Joy
’
s
communications
,
which
are
embraced
voluntarily
by
Bridget
from
what
Smith
would
call
her
sense
of
duty
—
she
“
enters
,
if
I
may
say
so
,
into
the
sentiments
of
that
divine
Being
”
(
Smith
,
TMS
,
276
).
In
the
allegory
,
those
communications
tell
Bridget
to
take
actions
rather
like
those
that
she
is
led
to
take
in
the
actual
world
,
from
market
signals
.
Cannan
suggests
that
the
market
conduces
to
socially
beneficial
actions
much
as
a
benevolent
system
of
superior
knowledge
,
communication
,
and
cooperation
would
.
Insights
Gained
by
Allegory
The
allegorical
talk
of
communication
empowers
us
to
formulate
questions
about
rules
and
institutions
,
questions
that
prove
wonderfully
fruitful
:
(
1
)
What
arrangements
generate
the
“
signals
”
that
best
“
communicate
”
what
to
do
?
Such
talk
gets
us
to
focus
on
what
the
relevant
signals
are
.
It
gets
us
to
focus
on
how
well
they
conduce
to
the
general
interest
.
It
helps
us
appreciate
how
“
com-
__________________________________________________________________
59
/index.php?action=ajax&rs=GDMgetPage&rsargs[]=LF-48.4 Klein.pdf&rsargs[]=2
__________________________________________________________________
munications
”
adjust
when
practices
go
wrong
.
(
2
)
If
the
signals
start
“
telling
”
people
to
go
in
the
wrong
direction
,
will
the
system
correct
itself
?
Will
it
tend
to
correct
errors
?
Indeed
,
it
is
allegory
that
gives
cogency
to
the
idea
of
“
market
error
”
or
“
social
error
.”
(
3
)
Will
the
system
tend
to
keep
up
with
changes
?
How
readily
and
reliably
will
it
“
communicate
”
instructions
to
adjust
to
changes
?
(
4
)
Will
it
dig
up
new
opportunity
,
new
matters
for
“
communication
”?
What
are
the
system
’
s
tendencies
to
discover
and
adopt
new
opportunities
for
advancing
the
good
of
the
whole
?
(
5
)
How
do
the
“
communicative
”
properties
of
the
system
fare
when
the
system
is
laden
with
governmental
restrictions
and
government-privileged
big
players
?
The
allegory
of
Joy
communicating
instructions
enables
one
to
reason
in
reference
to
the
perspective
of
one
who
has
superior
knowledge
and
purposes
that
we
go
along
with
—
even
while
we
emphasize
that
we
mere
mortals
do
not
have
such
knowledge
.
We
discuss
what
Joy
feels
about
what
she
sees
,
but
do
not
pretend
to
see
what
she
sees
.
Moreover
,
we
do
not
pretend
to
much
feel
what
she
feels
.
She
feels
universal
benevolence
.
We
cannot
and
do
not
.
One
’
s
pursuit
of
wisdom
and
virtue
is
not
so
much
the
aspiration
to
become
more
like
Joy
,
but
rather
to
become
more
like
those
who
,
it
seems
,
excel
in
advancing
what
she
finds
beautiful
.
Emulating
such
exemplars
,
we
do
our
duty
to
advance
universal
benevolence
.
The
Private
Enterprise
System
as
a
System
of
Cooperation
Many
had
suggested
that
the
economy
was
a
system
of
cooperation
,
including
Jeremy
Bentham
,
Thomas
Hodgskin
,
Richard
Whately
,
Frederic
Bastiat
,
William
Graham
Sumner
,
Henry
George
,
and
Philip
Wicksteed
.
We
find
such
talk
in
Milton
and
Rose
Friedman
’
s
Free
to
Choose
.
To
bring
the
tradition
down
to
today
,
let
’
s
turn
again
to
Cowen
and
Tabarrok
:
“
To
bring
just
one
product
to
your
table
requires
the
cooperative
effort
of
millions
.
Moreover
,
this
immense
cooperation
is
voluntary
and
undirected
.”
But
Karl
Marx
emphasized
that
the
system
,
in
its
immensity
,
was
not
cooperation
,
and
condemned
it
for
that
:
“[
A
]
ll
labour
in
which
many
individuals
cooperate
necessarily
requires
a
commanding
will
to
coordinate
and
unify
the
process
…
.
much
as
that
of
an
orchestra
conductor
”
(
Marx
,
1998
,
382
).
We
dispute
that
genuine
cooperation
depends
on
a
“
commanding
”
will
:
When
you
and
I
cooperate
in
making
lunch
,
we
scarcely
need
regard
anyone
’
s
will
as
“
commanding
.”
But
cooperation
does
entail
some
sense
of
direction
of
a
common
enterprise
,
to
which
we
mutually
contribute
.
Hayek
would
seem
to
concur
:
“
Cooperation
,
like
solidarity
,
presupposes
a
large
measure
of
agreement
on
ends
as
well
as
on
methods
employed
in
their
pursuit
.
It
makes
sense
in
a
small
group
whose
members
share
particular
habits
,
knowledge
and
beliefs
about
possibilities
”
(
1988
,
19
).
It
is
true
that
the
economy
in
all
its
immensity
entails
myriad
instances
of
cooperation
,
but
it
also
entails
myriad
instances
of
non-cooperation
.
It
entails
myriad
instances
of
abstention
,
of
deciding
not
to
cooperate
with
certain
parties
.
It
entails
myriad
instances
of
competition
__________________________________________________________________
60
/index.php?action=ajax&rs=GDMgetPage&rsargs[]=LF-48.4 Klein.pdf&rsargs[]=3
__________________________________________________________________
and
rivalry
.
It
entails
myriad
instances
of
rather
impersonal
exchange
that
,
as
cooperative
moments
,
are
tiny
and
often
ambivalent
.
It
entails
myriad
instances
of
ethically
ambiguous
moments
of
not
sharing
intelligence
.
It
entails
many
instances
of
deception
and
misrepresentation
.
It
entails
a
lot
of
things
,
not
just
instances
of
cooperation
.
Above
and
beyond
all
that
,
here
is
the
key
point
:
The
immensity
can
scarcely
be
said
to
constitute
a
common
enterprise
that
the
actors
share
a
mutual
sense
of
.
Unlike
genuine
cooperation
,
the
actors
do
not
have
any
mutual
sense
of
mutually
advancing
some
shared
goal
or
enterprise
.
Face
it
:
In
a
literal
sense
,
it
is
wrong
to
say
that
you
have
cooperated
with
the
myriad
people
who
contributed
to
the
production
of
the
pencil
or
the
woolen
coat
.
But
does
that
mean
we
should
surrender
the
useful
and
agreeable
talk
of
communication
and
cooperation
?
No
,
we
should
embrace
the
useful
and
agreeable
talk
.
But
we
should
recognize
that
it
is
not
literal
.
It
is
allegorical
.
We
can
affirm
the
cooperation
talk
:
In
an
allegory
,
individuals
communicate
with
Joy
and
voluntarily
follow
her
guidance
,
to
produce
a
pleasing
concatenation
of
activities
.
In
the
allegory
,
Joy
is
like
a
quarterback
with
whom
everyone
communicates
.
And
in
the
allegory
the
members
of
society
have
common
knowledge
that
each
communes
with
Joy
and
so
there
is
a
mutual
sense
of
advancing
the
coordination
of
a
vast
concatenation
of
their
actions
,
just
as
the
members
of
a
football
squad
have
common
knowledge
that
each
communicates
with
the
quarterback
and
there
is
a
mutual
sense
of
advancing
the
coordination
of
a
concatenation
of
their
actions
.
In
the
allegory
,
there
is
leadership
.
In
the
allegory
,
there
is
an
immense
cooperation
.
Then
,
when
we
turn
to
the
real-life
system
and
we
say
that
the
immense
system
is
“
a
system
of
cooperation
,”
we
mean
—
and
understand
that
we
mean
—
that
it
functions
somewhat
like
our
imagined
allegorical
system
of
cooperation
functions
.
The
Tragedy
of
Allegophobia
Adam
Smith
’
s
The
Theory
of
Moral
Sentiments
is
a
profoundly
allegorical
work
,
involving
such
formulations
as
“
the
man
within
the
breast
,”
“
the
impartial
spectator
,”
“
the
wisdom
of
nature
,”
and
“
universal
benevolence
.”
The
moral
and
political
judgments
of
TMS
were
openly
aesthetic
and
lacking
in
theoretical
foundations
.
Smith
died
in
1790
,
and
things
went
downhill
,
or
even
dropped
off
a
cliff
.
TMS
was
steadily
criticized
.
The
critics
recognized
that
TMS
lacks
foundations
.
The
critics
said
:
Science
,
real
knowledge
,
calls
for
foundations
,
not
allegory
;
it
calls
for
precision
and
accuracy
,
not
aesthetic
judgment
.
Not
long
after
Smith
’
s
death
the
work
fell
into
oblivion
,
and
reemerged
only
beginning
around
1980
,
once
enough
people
had
stopped
holding
its
non-foundationalism
against
it
.
During
that
long
oblivion
,
liberalism
was
led
principally
by
allegophobes
.
Like
any
phobia
,
allegophobia
is
deficient
in
self-awareness
and
self-understanding
.
While
touting
foundations
and
a
grammar-like
scientific
status
,
liberals
in
fact
wanted
poetry
,
too
.
Not
only
were
they
poets
who
didn
’
t
know
it
,
they
were
poets
who
denied
it
.
The
contrarieties
made
their
so-called
science
vulnerable
,
even
__________________________________________________________________
61
|
|